Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • COVID-19
    • Articles & podcasts
    • Blog posts
    • Collection
    • News
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • Classified ads
  • Authors
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
  • CMA Members
    • Overview for members
    • Earn CPD Credits
    • Print copies of CMAJ
    • Career Ad Discount
  • Subscribers
    • General information
    • View prices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN

User menu

Search

  • Advanced search
CMAJ
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN
CMAJ

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • COVID-19
    • Articles & podcasts
    • Blog posts
    • Collection
    • News
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • Classified ads
  • Authors
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
  • CMA Members
    • Overview for members
    • Earn CPD Credits
    • Print copies of CMAJ
    • Career Ad Discount
  • Subscribers
    • General information
    • View prices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
  • Visit CMAJ on Facebook
  • Follow CMAJ on Twitter
  • Follow CMAJ on Pinterest
  • Follow CMAJ on Youtube
  • Follow CMAJ on Instagram
Commentary

The modern scientific physician: 5. The useful property of an intervention

Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ October 16, 2001 165 (8) 1059-1060;
Olli S. Miettinen
Dr. Miettinen is with the Department of Epidemiology and Biostatistics and the Department of Medicine, Faculty of Medicine, McGill University, Montreal, Que., and also with the Department of Medicine, Weill Medical College, Cornell University, New York, NY.
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

The modern scientific physician is well familiar with ‘the scripture’ on the putatively meaningful ‘properties’ of diagnostics, with medical textbooks, for example Harrison's,1 among the sources. Critically reflective as (s)he inherently is, (s)he may nevertheless have come to the succedaneous view that a diagnostic actually has just one useful property: marginal informativeness — critical to consider in deciding whether to invoke the diagnostic, but irrelevant in interpreting the result it produces. This useful property of a diagnostic contrasts with effectiveness, the useful property of an intervention.

That diagnostic versus intervention duality, resulting in the informativeness versus effectiveness duality in the useful properties of medical procedures, is denied in the corresponding monistic idea that a quarter-century ago was adopted and subsequently was propagated — until its recent dismantling — by the Office of Technology Assessment of the US Congress. In effect denying the diagnosis versus prognosis duality that has prevailed in medicine ever since Hippocrates, the Office of Technology Assessment quite cavalierly adopted the view that diagnostics, too, are invoked to change the course of health (for the better); and that therefore they, too, are interventions, with effectiveness their useful property.2 In the Office of Technology Assessment's realm of medical “technology assessment” this idea brought diagnostics to the scope of its intervention-centred interests in medical “outcomes research,” which the Office of Technology Assessment itself recently recast as “effectiveness research.”3 The leadership of American radiology embraced these aberrations from central and ingrained concepts of medicine,4,5 and even the US National Cancer Institute went along with this in quite a spectacular way.6

Nevertheless, the modern scientific physician still holds that Roentgen did not provide for inventing an effective intervention for pulmonary tuberculosis; that the advent of its foundation truly was marked by the discovery of streptomycin, by Waksman and his co-workers much later. The use of a diagnostic, (s)he understands, is invoked to enhance knowing about the present, diagnosis — in part for the purpose of thereby knowing about the future, prognosis. An intervention, by contrast, is not invoked for the purpose of any type of knowing but to change the future for the better, through the intended effect of the intervention. Etymologically, intervention is coming in-between — a feature not of diagnostics but of preventives, therapeutics and rehabilitation. (In medicine, an intervention is intended to come between stages of the ‘natural history’ of health or illness.)

The Office of Technology Assessment also introduced the now quite widely held notion that an important distinction is to be made between effectiveness and efficacy. As it most recently again expressed this distinction, effectiveness putatively is a matter of whether an intervention improves health “under ordinary circumstances, in ordinary settings,” while efficacy putatively is the counterpart of this “under ideal circumstances.”7 This distinction-making is not altogether surprising when it is realized that “medical technology” to the Office of Technology Assessment consisted of entities such as “drugs”8 instead of suitably defined techniques/algorithms of intervention (involving drugs or whatever agents of intended change) on suitably defined indications. (In scholarly terms, neither drugs nor drug uses are technologies; drug development is.9)

I once asked an exceptionally scientific surgeon (John Kirklin) how he thinks about surgeons' variable skills as a determinant of outcome in surgical research toward knowledge to guide practice (under whatever circumstances). His retort was that the so-called “good surgeon” to him is one who uses a good technique, and the so-called “bad surgeon” correspondingly one who uses a bad technique; that what matters is the scientifically necessary specificity on all relevant particulars of the surgical technique used (e.g., pump time in coronary bypass surgery); and that conditionally on these specifics, the surgeon's skill is scientifically a nonissue (and merely a determinant of what variant of the generic technique gets to be used). The same imperative of specificity he naturally would have extended to the intervention's indication. As for effectiveness versus efficacy, there thus was no such distinction in the mind of this genuinely scientific physician.

Science is characterized not only by its generalizations (particularistic to abstract) but also by the distinctions that it makes in these. In particular, any quantitative idea about effectiveness must involve the requisite degree of specificity to subtypes of both the intervention (degree of adherence to the plan included) and the indication (recipient of the intervention). In these terms the effectiveness versus efficacy distinction indeed does vanish. Consonant with this, the terms “effectiveness” and “efficacy” are synonyms in general English; and so they also were in the mind of the original and highly esteemed advocate of directly practice-relevant effectiveness research on health-care interventions, conducted under the ideal circumstances of randomized trials.10

Integral to the concept of a medical intervention's effectiveness is, naturally, the course or outcome that the intervention is to change; and to this, too, the Office of Technology Assessment's “outcomes research” interest brought an innovation: the notion that measures of “health-related quality of life” need to be included.11 The modern scientific physician, however, likely still prefers the traditional idea that the intended effects of medical interventions are somatic, inclusive of their patient-relevant in-vivo manifestations (in reduced discomfort, deformity and/or dysfunctionality); and that welcome changes in quality of life — psychologic12 — are secondary to these, matters not really of medicine per se but of the utility — subjective — of the somatic effects to the person at issue. Further, (s)he inclines to take the view that insofar as these quality of life implications of genuinely medical states/events call for, and are subject to, research, they are to be studied as attributes of health states/events themselves, irrespective of the role that any intervention may have had in bringing these about.

Central to the Office of Technology Assessment's concerns with medical interventions was “cost-effectiveness analysis” of these13; and central to this, in turn, is taken to be an intervention's effectiveness in terms of its resultant gain in “quality-adjusted life years.”14 For this measure, health-related quality of life is defined on a quantitative scale in which “1 corresponds to perfect health and ... 0 corresponds to a health state judged equivalent to death.”15 The scientific physician's intellect faces a serious challenge in attempting to apprehend the concept of health-related quality of life that is “equivalent to death,” and equally if its zero value actually is taken to characterize the health aspects of life post-mortem!

Puzzling, too, is the related ‘cost-effectiveness analysis’ idea that an intervention's ‘expected’ — average — effect on the duration (quality-adjusted) of life — and thus effect on ‘life expectancy’ (quality-adjusted) — is appropriate to use as the measure of its effectiveness. For, with or without intervention, a person faces a chance duration of life; and only one of the possibilities will become the reality, not their probability-weighted average. If an intervention indeed prolonged the person's actual duration of life by the ‘expected’ amount, it generally would have minimal utility to him/her; but the chance utility is different, generally much higher. Buying a lottery ticket, or insurance for that matter, is characterized by a negative ‘expected’ effect on a person's finances; but rational people nevertheless see such choices as financially justifiable for their individual purposes, mindful of what might turn out to be their particular luck or lot. If a young scientific physician has an acute illness characterized by 1% case-fatality rate in the absence of an available, fully curative (but perhaps very expensive) intervention, (s)he — and the society just the same — attaches a much higher utility to curing that illness than to avoiding a 1% shortening of his/her actual lifespan (conditional on surviving that illness).

The concepts of intervention and its effectiveness, and the terms in which to quantify the latter, may appear to be obvious to a physician, and indeed they should be. But the modern scientific physician actually has a lot to think about in this context, now that the effectiveness of medical interventions has become a concern also to professionals other than physicians. As with ideas intrinsic to medicine itself, (s)he does not simply believe the exogenous ideas, taking them for granted; in the Baconian spirit16 (s)he weighs and considers them — and even in this now-multidisciplinary context ultimately alone.

Articles to date in this series
  • Miettinen OS. The modern scientific physician: 1. Can practice be science? CMAJ 2001;165(4):441-2.

  • Miettinen OS. The modern scientific physician: 2. Medical science versus scientific medicine. CMAJ 2001; 165(5): 591-2.

  • Miettinen OS. The modern scientific physician: 3. Scientific diagnosis. CMAJ 2001;165(6):781-2.

  • Miettinen OS. The modern scientific physician: 4. The useful property of a diagnostic. CMAJ 2001;165 (7): 910-1.

  • Miettinen OS. The modern scientific physician: 5. The useful property of an intervention. CMAJ 2001;165(8):1059-60.

Footnotes

  • Competing interests: None declared.

References

  1. 1.↵
    Goldman L. Quantitative aspects of clinical reasoning. In: Fanci AS, Braunwald E, Isselbacher KJ, Wilson JD, Martin JB, Kasper DL, et al., editors. Harrison's. Principles of internal medicine. 14th ed. vol 1. New York: McGraw-Hill; 1998. p. 9-14.
  2. 2.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Assessing the efficacy and safety of medical technologies. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1978. Report no.: OTA-H-75. p. 14.
  3. 3.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Identifying health technologies that work. Searching for evidence. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1994. Report no.: OTA-H-678. p. 23.
  4. 4.↵
    Thornbury JR. Why should radiologists be interested in technology assessment and outcomes research? AJR Am J Roentgenol 1994;163:1027-30.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  5. 5.↵
    Hillman B. Outcomes research and cost-effectiveness analysis for diagnostic imaging research [editorial]. Radiology 1994;193:307-10.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  6. 6.↵
    Hillman BJ, Gatsonis C, Sullivan DC. American College of Radiology Imaging Network: new national cooperative group for conducting clinical trials of medical imaging technologies. Radiology 1999;213:641-5.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  7. 7.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Identifying health technologies that work. Searching for evidence. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1994. Report no.: OTA-H-678. p. 4.
  8. 8.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Identifying health technologies that work. Searching for evidence. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1994. Report no.: OTA-H-678. p. 1.
  9. 9.↵
    Niiniluoto I. Remarks on technologic progress. In: Niiniluoto I. Is science progressive? Dortrecht (the Netherlands): D Reidel Publishing Company; 1984. p. 260.
  10. 10.↵
    Cochrane AL. Effectiveness and efficiency. Random reflections on health services. London: Nuttfield Provincial Hospitals Trust; 1972. p. 2.
  11. 11.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. Identifying health technologies that work. Searching for evidence. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1994. Report no.: OTA-H-678. p. 40-3.
  12. 12.↵
    Epstein A. The outcomes movement — will it take us where we want to go? N Engl J Med 1990;323:266-70.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. 13.↵
    US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment. The state of cost-effectiveness analysis. In: Identifying health technologies that work. Searching for evidence. Washington: US Government Printing Office; 1994. Report no.: OTA-H-678. p. 107-30.
  14. 14.↵
    Gold MR, Siegel JE, Russell LB, Weinstein MC, editors. Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 1996.
  15. 15.↵
    Gold MR, Siegel JE, Russell LB, Weinstein MC, editors. Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 1996. p. 29, cf. 88.
  16. 16.↵
    Vickers B, editor. Francis Bacon. The essays or counsels civil and moral. New York: Oxford University Press; 1999. p. 114, 134.
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

CMAJ
Vol. 165, Issue 8
16 Oct 2001
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author

Article tools

Respond to this article
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
To sign up for email alerts or to access your current email alerts, enter your email address below:
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on CMAJ.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
The modern scientific physician: 5. The useful property of an intervention
(Your Name) has sent you a message from CMAJ
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the CMAJ web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
The modern scientific physician: 5. The useful property of an intervention
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Oct 2001, 165 (8) 1059-1060;

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
‍ Request Permissions
Share
The modern scientific physician: 5. The useful property of an intervention
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Oct 2001, 165 (8) 1059-1060;
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

  • No related articles found.
  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Google Scholar

More in this TOC Section

  • Not neutral: reimagining antiracism as a professional competence
  • Transforming race-based health research in Canada
  • Time to dismantle systemic anti-Black racism in medicine in Canada
Show more Commentary

Similar Articles

Content

  • Current issue
  • Past issues
  • Collections
  • Sections
  • Blog
  • Podcasts
  • Alerts
  • RSS
  • Early releases

Information for

  • Advertisers
  • Authors
  • Reviewers
  • CMA Members
  • Media
  • Reprint requests
  • Subscribers

About

  • General Information
  • Journal staff
  • Editorial Board
  • Governance Council
  • Journal Oversight
  • Careers
  • Contact
  • Copyright and Permissions

Copyright 2021, Joule Inc. or its licensors. All rights reserved. ISSN 1488-2329 (e) 0820-3946 (p)

All editorial matter in CMAJ represents the opinions of the authors and not necessarily those of the Canadian Medical Association or its subsidiaries.

Powered by HighWire