Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • COVID-19 articles
    • Obituary notices
  • Authors & Reviewers
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
    • Open access
    • Patient engagement
  • Physicians & Subscribers
    • Benefits for Canadian physicians
    • CPD Credits for CMA Members
    • Subscribe to CMAJ digital
    • Subscribe to CMAJ print
    • Subscription prices
    • Obituary notices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
    • Trousse média 2023
    • Avis de décès
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN

User menu

Search

  • Advanced search
CMAJ
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN
CMAJ

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • COVID-19 articles
    • Obituary notices
  • Authors & Reviewers
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
    • Open access
    • Patient engagement
  • Physicians & Subscribers
    • Benefits for Canadian physicians
    • CPD Credits for CMA Members
    • Subscribe to CMAJ digital
    • Subscribe to CMAJ print
    • Subscription prices
    • Obituary notices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
    • Trousse média 2023
    • Avis de décès
  • Visit CMAJ on Facebook
  • Follow CMAJ on Twitter
  • Follow CMAJ on Instagram
  • Listen to CMAJ podcasts
Commentary

The modern scientific physician: 3. Scientific diagnosis

Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ September 18, 2001 165 (6) 781-782;
Olli S. Miettinen
Dr. Miettinen is with the Department of Epidemiology and Biostatistics and the Department of Medicine, Faculty of Medicine, McGill University, Montreal, Que., and also with the Department of Medicine, Weill Medical College, Cornell University, New York, NY.
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Central to the practice of medicine is, of course, diagnosis. In the process of pursuing diagnosis, facts about the situation are secured. At any given stage of the process, the available facts define the corresponding diagnostic profile. In this, the facts fall in two conceptually distinct categories. Some of them have to do with manifestations of the underlying illness (unknown, pathologically defined); and for any given potential manifestation considered, the available fact is either ‘positive’ or ‘negative’ (to one extent or another). The other facts concern determinants of the patient's ‘risk’ — propensity — now to have whatever particular underlying illness whose presence is consistent with the known pattern of manifestations. Part of the propensity profile may refer to the rate of occurrence of the illness at issue, or to determinants of this, in the person's environment in the etiologic period of time. The profile as a whole is consistent with each of a particular, knowable set of possible underlying illnesses, constituting the differential-diagnostic set at that stage of the diagnostic process.

It is now well-established that, when focussing on any given illness in the differential-diagnostic set, the proper concern is to arrive at an appropriate probability of its presence (as an explanation of the manifestation profile, notably of the positive elements in it). But, how to go about this rationally, as is required in scientific diagnosis?

Learned diagnosticians know what has been written about the principles of this probability-setting. The seminal paper on this, they know, was published by a dentist together with a radiologist in 1959.1 It introduced the idea that the proper theoretical framework for setting diagnostic probabilities is Bayes' theorem, with ‘prior probability’ (based on the propensity profile) and the manifestation profile's ‘likelihood ratio’ as inputs to the calculation of the probability. They also know that ‘clinical epidemiologists,’ while committed to this basic idea, have relaxed the theoretical assumptions and, on this basis, adopted a simplified modification of it: applying Bayes' theorem sequentially across the entire diagnostic profile.2 If uncritical, they believe and take for granted the basic idea and the putative justifiability of the modification.

A genuinely scientific diagnostician, however, not only knows prevailing ideas but also reflects critically on them. In the mental habit of all scholars, (s)he begins with critical examination of the concepts involved. Central among these is likelihood: the probability of, or probability density at, the manifestational profile, conditional on the presence/absence of the illness at issue. How can this be known, (s)he wonders, as scientific study of it would require assembling a series (large, representative) of cases of that illness, and also of its differential-diagnostic alternatives, independently of the profiles which in reality bring the cases to clinical attention? Doesn't the likelihood vary among subtypes of the illness, by severity for example? Isn't the number of possible profiles too large to meaningfully learn about? (S)he comes to realize that serious problems abound.3

(S)he thus finds it necessary, as indeed scholars in general do in situations like this, to ask the fundamental question: what really is the principal concept at issue — here that of the diagnostic probability to be quantified, notably the concept of the correct diagnostic probability of the presence of the particular illness being considered? For, (s)he knows that scientific answers tend naturally to ‘flow’ from conceptually appropriate questions.4 And, if able to clear the mind of rote learning, (s)he readily comes to a simple realization: if I knew the proportion in which the illness is present in instances like this (ones with this propensity and manifestation profile) in general (in the abstract) — its prevalence in this sense — then I would take that proportion to be the correct diagnostic probability in this particular instance of the profile.

This realization leads the diagnostician to ask the correct question — that prevalence question — pertaining to the correct diagnostic probability in the context of the profile at hand. And as for the theoretical framework beyond this critical point of departure, the principles indeed flow from the prevalence concept of correct probability. The obvious concern is to know, for a suitably defined diagnostic domain (broadly by range of age and generic type of main complaint, say), that prevalence as a joint function of the set of diagnostic indicators involved (pertaining to actual age, particulars of the main complaint, etc.), and to evaluate this function at the diagnostic profile. With this outlook, together with modern statistical theory, the proper theoretical framework is understood to be that of logistic regression models for defined domains. For example, a truly modern scientific radiologist, when concerned to set the probability of the presence of pulmonary embolism (PE) in the context of the result from the ventilation-perfusion test, thinks in terms of a suitable logistic regression model expressing the prevalence of PE as a joint function of the relevant descriptors of the obtained image, this in an appropriate domain of suspicion of PE's presence; and (s)he deploys a fitted model of this type,5 evaluating it at the facts from the image at hand.

The most specifically diagnosis-oriented specialty in clinical medicine is, at present, radiology; and this specialty indeed has been at the forefront of the development of the theoretical framework for diagnosis. Largely from radiology came, as I noted, the idea (mistaken) that Bayes' theorem is the necessary theoretical framework. More recently, leading radiologists have advanced another, even more misguided idea: that diagnostic imaging — they still focus on their own genre of diagnostics in this — actually is intervention; and from the adoption of this malformed concept they naturally have taken to flow the idea that imaging actually is supposed to have health-improving efficacy or effectiveness6 — to be assessed by a comparative study, ideally a randomized controlled trial.7

One leader of today's radiology recently posited the precept that “tomorrow's radiologists need to be critical thinkers, learning to read books and journals and to listen to ‘experts’ more sceptically”.8 How true of colleagues in this specialty when reading their own leaders' writings on the concepts and principles of scientific diagnosis and on the theory of research toward its knowledge base, and equally of whatever specialists studying internists' and others' writings on ‘clinical epidemiology.’ A pre-eminent leader in everything scholarly, much earlier, advised all of us to “Read not to contradict and confute; nor to believe and take for granted; nor to find talk and discourse; but to weigh and consider.”9

Footnotes

  • Competing interests: None declared.

References

  1. 1.↵
    Ledley RS, Lusted LB. Reasoning foundations of medical diagnosis. Science 1959;130:9-21.
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  2. 2.↵
    Sackett DL, Haynes RB, Gyatt GH, Tugwell P. Clinical epidemiology. A basic science for clinical medicine. 2nd ed. Boston: Little, Brown and Company; 1991. p. 131-9.
  3. 3.↵
    Miettinen OS, Caro JJ. Foundations of medical diagnosis: what actually are the parameters involved in Bayes' theorem? Stat Med 1994;13:201-9.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  4. 4.↵
    Berlin I. The proper study of mankind. London: Chatto & Windus; 1997. p. 63.
  5. 5.↵
    Miettinen OS, Henschke CI, Yankelevitz DF. Evaluation of diagnostic imaging tests: diagnostic probability estimation. J Clin Epidemiol 1998;51:1293-8.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  6. 6.↵
    Fryback DG, Thornbury JR. The efficacy of diagnostic imaging. Med Decis Making 1991;11:88-94.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  7. 7.↵
    Hillman BJ, Gatsonis C, Sullivan DC. American College of Radiology Imaging Network: new national cooperative group for conducting clinical trials of medical imaging technologies. Radiology 1999;213:641-5.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  8. 8.↵
    Hillman BJ. Medical imaging in the 21st century. Lancet 1997;350:731-3.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  9. 9.↵
    Vickers B, editor. Francis Bacon. The essays or counsels civil and moral. New York: Oxford University Press; 1999. p. 114.
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

CMAJ
Vol. 165, Issue 6
18 Sep 2001
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author

Article tools

Respond to this article
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
To sign up for email alerts or to access your current email alerts, enter your email address below:
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on CMAJ.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
The modern scientific physician: 3. Scientific diagnosis
(Your Name) has sent you a message from CMAJ
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the CMAJ web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
The modern scientific physician: 3. Scientific diagnosis
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Sep 2001, 165 (6) 781-782;

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
‍ Request Permissions
Share
The modern scientific physician: 3. Scientific diagnosis
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Sep 2001, 165 (6) 781-782;
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

  • No related articles found.
  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Google Scholar

More in this TOC Section

  • How can Canada’s health systems improve care for people with chronic obstructive pulmonary disease?
  • Minimally invasive procedures in gender-affirming care: the case for public funding across Canada
  • Time for Canada to align with global innovations in treatment for tuberculosis
Show more Commentary

Similar Articles

 

View Latest Classified Ads

Content

  • Current issue
  • Past issues
  • Collections
  • Sections
  • Blog
  • Podcasts
  • Alerts
  • RSS
  • Early releases

Information for

  • Advertisers
  • Authors
  • Reviewers
  • CMA Members
  • CPD credits
  • Media
  • Reprint requests
  • Subscribers

About

  • General Information
  • Journal staff
  • Editorial Board
  • Advisory Panels
  • Governance Council
  • Journal Oversight
  • Careers
  • Contact
  • Copyright and Permissions
CMAJ Group

Copyright 2023, CMA Impact Inc. or its licensors. All rights reserved. ISSN 1488-2329 (e) 0820-3946 (p)

All editorial matter in CMAJ represents the opinions of the authors and not necessarily those of the Canadian Medical Association or its subsidiaries.

To receive any of these resources in an accessible format, please contact us at CMAJ Group, 500-1410 Blair Towers Place, Ottawa ON, K1J 9B9; p: 1-888-855-2555; e: [email protected]

CMA Civility, Accessibility, Privacy

 

Powered by HighWire