Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • COVID-19 articles
    • Obituary notices
  • Authors & Reviewers
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
    • Open access
    • Patient engagement
  • Physicians & Subscribers
    • Benefits for Canadian physicians
    • CPD Credits for CMA Members
    • Subscribe to CMAJ digital
    • Subscribe to CMAJ print
    • Subscription prices
    • Obituary notices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
    • Trousse média 2023
    • Avis de décès
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN

User menu

Search

  • Advanced search
CMAJ
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
    • JPN
CMAJ

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Content
    • Current issue
    • Past issues
    • Early releases
    • Collections
    • Sections
    • Blog
    • Infographics & illustrations
    • Podcasts
    • COVID-19 articles
    • Obituary notices
  • Authors & Reviewers
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission guidelines
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Forms
    • Editorial process
    • Editorial policies
    • Peer review process
    • Publication fees
    • Reprint requests
    • Open access
    • Patient engagement
  • Physicians & Subscribers
    • Benefits for Canadian physicians
    • CPD Credits for CMA Members
    • Subscribe to CMAJ digital
    • Subscribe to CMAJ print
    • Subscription prices
    • Obituary notices
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • JAMC
    • À propos
    • Numéro en cours
    • Archives
    • Sections
    • Abonnement
    • Alertes
    • Trousse média 2023
    • Avis de décès
  • Visit CMAJ on Facebook
  • Follow CMAJ on Twitter
  • Follow CMAJ on Instagram
  • Listen to CMAJ podcasts
Commentary

The modern scientific physician: 2. Medical science versus scientific medicine

Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ September 04, 2001 165 (5) 591-592;
Olli S. Miettinen
Dr. Miettinen is with the Department of Epidemiology and Biostatistics and the Department of Medicine, Faculty of Medicine, McGill University, Montreal, Que., and also with the Department of Medicine, Weill Medical College, Cornell University, New York, NY.
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Sharply contrasting with the Aesculapian god-physician, his Hippocratic contemporary was learned, wise, modest and humane.1 These qualities defining the Hippocratic ideal remain unquestioned for today's purposes just the same, but realizing them has become more challenging upon the advent of medical science. Learnedness is strained in attempting to apprehend the concept of science; modesty is brought into question by the affected habit of wearing the scientist's laboratory coat; both learnedness and modesty are wanting when actually confusing the practice of scientific medicine with medical science itself; modesty together with humaneness are threatened by the role of medical science in providing for the arrogant claims of “cultural authority” for medicine2 and of medical knowledge being beyond the reach of lay understanding2; and wisdom is challenged to understand “the ends of life” in the context of the expanded opportunities brought about by increase in knowledge.3

The famous Flexner report that defined medical education for the United States and Canada in 1910 drew its ideas principally from the culture that prevailed at Johns Hopkins University at the time, with Osler among its illustrious leaders in medicine. According to that report, “The essence of science is its method, — the painstaking collection of all relevant data, the severe effort to read their significance in connection.”4 The report propagated the idea that the then-modern — avant-garde, actually — practice of medicine had this very essence, and that it therefore was not merely scientific but indeed science proper. For example, the essence of diagnosis that qualified it as science was said to be its requisite degree of “caution and thoroughness” with which “observations are made, inferences are drawn, and the results are heeded.”4 This conception of the essence of science contrasts sharply with that in the philosophy of science.5

Leaders of today's Evidence-based Medicine (EBM) movement explain their idea about modern practice vis-à-vis science in a textbook of “clinical epidemiology”6: “At different times, and in different situations, it dawned on each of us that there was, in fact, a science to the art of medicine,” namely “clinical epidemiology,” a source of principles to guide diagnosis and prognosis (including as to intervention effects) and thus a “basic science” for clinical practice.7 Diagnosis, they point out, is “an element” in this “science of the art of medicine.”8 Hippocrates already was committed to practice according to principles, rational principles, and so is, of course, the modern scientific physician. If today's ‘clinical epidemiology’ actually does amount to codified and tenable — rational — principles of diagnosis etc., this does not, however, qualify it as a science,5 to say nothing about its application, or that of whatever actual science, making practice science.9

To grasp the genuine essence of medical science, it is good to recall the familiar, simple yet epoch-opening work of Jenner. He inoculated that 8-year-old boy with pus from his sister's cowpox lesion and, some months later, gave him a smallpox inoculation; and behold: the boy did not come down with smallpox! Jenner documented this experience for the relevant scientific community, for it to judge the significance of the experience beyond those documented facts (particularistic, i.e., spatio-temporarally specific), specifically for it to judge the experience's meaning in the abstract (i.e., without a referent in place or time), its role in thus contributing to scientific knowledge (about nature, in the abstract). Neither clinical diagnosis nor community-medicine morbidity survey — or health-care description/evaluation (fact-finding, particularistic10) for that matter — satisfies this first-order requirement for a piece of work to be one of science.

While those actions, and intentions beyond personally having the documented experience, were essential to making Jenner's work a matter of science, equally essential was the fact that his documentation actually was received and examined by the relevant community of scientists. For, essential to science also is its co-operative and public character11 and its recourse to “evidence as an objective factor [italics mine] inviting universal examination and compelling ultimate unanimity.”12 Thus qualified, Jenner's work would have been science even if it had failed to advance scientific knowledge (i.e., belief that is intersubjective — shared among experts — by definition11); only, in this case it would have been unsuccessful science. Science, thus understood, aims to produce knowledge (abstract), while practice deploys knowledge (in the context of ad hoc facts).

It deserves note and indeed emphasis that in medicine, just as in farming for example, deployed is much abstract knowledge of empirical yet nonscientific origin. It was informal experience in actual practice, not medical science, that gave physicians the knowledge base for, say, the prevention of ‘contagion’ (Fracastorius, 1546) and the treatment of various injuries — long before the advent of medical science.

While the modern scientific physician is no more committed to rationality than Hippocrates was, fundamentally novel in modern medicine are two implications of the recent advent of medical science. For one, the availability of knowledge from medical science provides, increasingly, a superior substitute for that from informal experience as for the substantive inputs in whatever presumedly rational framework. Reliance on personal experience, while still much touted, is irrational; collective informal experience is preferable but still quite wanting (cf. venesection); and ultimate preference is rationally to be given to evidence from scientific experience — though not in the EBM style of its personal interpretation but in terms of the scientific knowledge (intersubjective) that it has led to. For another, available to the modern scientific physician are many products of medical technology, the development of which has been provided for by progress in medical and other science.

In respect to rationality itself, so centrally a required feature of scientific medicine, the learned and suitably modest practitioner of scientific medicine does not equate it with plain common sense — natural logic as distinct from scientific, acquired logic.13 Moreover, even erudite writings on the concepts and principles — theory — of medicine (s)he reads as instructed by Bacon: “Read not to contradict, nor to believe, but to weigh and consider.”14 When this Baconian habit has become widespread and has led to quite comprehensive and broadly agreed-upon concepts and logically tenable principles, and when the latter are broadly heeded, then and only then has medicine at large become genuinely rational. This has not yet happened, in part because “The dream of reason did not take power into account.”15

However uniformly committed to scientific practice modern physicians may be, modern practice actually is scientific only to the extent to which its theoretical framework truly is rational and scientific knowledge is deployed in such a framework.

Footnotes

  • The first article in this series appeared in the Aug. 21, 2001, issue of CMAJ (page 441).

    Competing interests: None declared.

References

  1. 1.↵
    Marti-Ibanez F, editor. The epic of medicine. New York: Clarkson N Potter; 1962. p. 66.
  2. 2.↵
    Starr P. The social transformation of American medicine. The rise of a sovereign profession and the making of a vast industry. New York: Basic Books; 1982. p. 59.
  3. 3.↵
    Russell B. The scientific outlook. London: Allen & Unwin; 1931. p. x.
  4. 4.↵
    Flexner A. Medical education in the United States and Canada. Bulletin no. 4. New York: Carnegie Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching; 1910. p. 92.
  5. 5.↵
    Niiniluoto I. The nature of science. In: Niiniluoto I. Is science progressive? Dortrecht (the Netherlands): D Reidel Publishing Company; 1984. p. 1-9.
  6. 6.↵
    Sackett DL, Richardson WS, Rosenberg W, Haynes RB. Evidence-based medicine. How to practice and teach EBM. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone; 1998. p. vi.
  7. 7.↵
    Sackett DL, Haynes RB, Gyatt GH, Tugwell P. Clinical epidemiology. A basic science for clinical medicine. 2nd ed. Boston: Little, Brown and Company; 1991. p. ix.
  8. 8.↵
    Sackett DL, Haynes RB, Gyatt GH, Tugwell P. Clinical epidemiology. A basic science for clinical medicine. 2nd ed. Boston: Little, Brown and Company; 1991. p. 93.
  9. 9.↵
    Niiniluoto I. Is science progressive? Dortrecht (the Netherlands): D Reidel Publishing Company; 1984. p. 237-8.
  10. 10.↵
    Liberati A, Chatziandreou E, Miettinen O. Health care research: what is it about? Qual Assur Health Care 1989;1:249-57.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  11. 11.↵
    Niiniluoto I. Is science progressive? Dortrecht (the Netherlands): D Reidel Publishing Company; 1984. p. 4.
  12. 12.↵
    Buchler J, editor. Philosophical writings of Peirce. New York: Dover Publications; 1955. p. x.
  13. 13.↵
    McCall RJ. Basic logic. 2nd ed. New York: Barnes & Noble; 1952. p. xix.
  14. 14.↵
    Bacon F. Essays, 1597. In: Vickers B, editor. Francis Bacon. The essays or counsels civil and moral. New York: Oxford University Press; 1999. p. 134.
  15. 15.↵
    Starr P. The social transformation of American medicine. The rise of a sovereign profession and the making of a vast industry. New York: Basic Books; 1982. p. 3.
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

CMAJ
Vol. 165, Issue 5
4 Sep 2001
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author

Article tools

Respond to this article
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
To sign up for email alerts or to access your current email alerts, enter your email address below:
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on CMAJ.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
The modern scientific physician: 2. Medical science versus scientific medicine
(Your Name) has sent you a message from CMAJ
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the CMAJ web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
The modern scientific physician: 2. Medical science versus scientific medicine
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Sep 2001, 165 (5) 591-592;

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
‍ Request Permissions
Share
The modern scientific physician: 2. Medical science versus scientific medicine
Olli S. Miettinen
CMAJ Sep 2001, 165 (5) 591-592;
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

  • No related articles found.
  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Revisiting the modern scientific physician
  • Google Scholar

More in this TOC Section

  • How can Canada’s health systems improve care for people with chronic obstructive pulmonary disease?
  • Minimally invasive procedures in gender-affirming care: the case for public funding across Canada
  • Time for Canada to align with global innovations in treatment for tuberculosis
Show more Commentary

Similar Articles

 

View Latest Classified Ads

Content

  • Current issue
  • Past issues
  • Collections
  • Sections
  • Blog
  • Podcasts
  • Alerts
  • RSS
  • Early releases

Information for

  • Advertisers
  • Authors
  • Reviewers
  • CMA Members
  • CPD credits
  • Media
  • Reprint requests
  • Subscribers

About

  • General Information
  • Journal staff
  • Editorial Board
  • Advisory Panels
  • Governance Council
  • Journal Oversight
  • Careers
  • Contact
  • Copyright and Permissions
CMAJ Group

Copyright 2023, CMA Impact Inc. or its licensors. All rights reserved. ISSN 1488-2329 (e) 0820-3946 (p)

All editorial matter in CMAJ represents the opinions of the authors and not necessarily those of the Canadian Medical Association or its subsidiaries.

To receive any of these resources in an accessible format, please contact us at CMAJ Group, 500-1410 Blair Towers Place, Ottawa ON, K1J 9B9; p: 1-888-855-2555; e: [email protected]

CMA Civility, Accessibility, Privacy

 

Powered by HighWire